Gibilisco 2021, “Decentralization, Repression, and Gambling for Unity”
Trying a new thing where I put a bit more structure on my personal notes about papers I teach, to make those notes suitable for public consumption.
Gibilisco (2021) studies a central tradeoff for the use of repression against secessionist movements — or, really, against marginalized political groups generally. Repression may help the government maintain control now, but it threatens the government’s future power by generating grievances in the repressed group. As grievances increase, so does the populace’s ability to organize for collective action against oppressive rule. Indefinite repression makes an autocrat’s job harder and harder, as the threat of collective resistance becomes more and more credible. The paper builds a formal model around this tradeoff, analyzing the dynamics of governance and grievance.
The most striking result here is that the government may sometimes “gamble for unity”, refraining from repression despite knowing the populace will mobilize against central control. The key insight is that just as grievances may build up with repression, they may also dissipate in the absence of repression. By tolerating some danger to its control in the short run, the government can wait for grievances to get low enough that the dissenters no longer have a credible threat to mobilize opposition. This could end badly for the ruler, with the government losing control in a costly revolution. But if the government is lucky enough to weather the temporary storm, then it is sure to maintain control without even having to use repressive measures.
This paper is an impressive example of how to model strategic interaction in politics without committing to a narrow homo economicus model of human motivation (e.g., Ashworth and Bueno de Mesquita 2014). Repression makes people mad, and that anger persists over time. It’s coherent to acknowledge that emotions play a real role in public responses to repression and that strategic calculations play a role too. If nothing else, I love this paper for knocking down the notion of opportunistic “greed” and irrational “grievance” as mutually exclusive explanations for civil conflict.
Formal model
Two players, Center and Periphery, interact over infinite discrete periods. Each period
In an active period, the Center first chooses whether to grant independence to the Periphery, repress the Periphery, or do nothing (“hands off”). The sequence of actions from there depends on the Center’s initial choice:
If the Center granted independence, then the game moves to the independence state, and all subsequent periods are inactive.
If the Center repressed, then it retains control this period and there are no further choices to make. Grievances increase next period:
.If the Center did nothing, then the Periphery chooses whether to mobilize for secession. If it does, then it wins — moving the game to the independence state — with probability
, a nondecreasing function of the current grievance level.If the Center mobilizes and loses, or if it doesn’t mobilize, then the game remains active next period. Grievances decrease next period, unless there were none already:
.
Gibilisco assumes
At the end of any period where C still controls the territory, C receives
If mobilization occurs and succeeds, C suffers an additional cost
Gibilisco imposes two assumptions to focus on interesting cases of the model.
We’ll work backward to get to the assumption. Imagine that P would decline to mobilize every period, even with very high grievances. Then P’s payoff would be
We’ll work backward again. Suppose grievances are arbitrarily high, C goes hands-off every period, and P mobilizes every period. C’s long-run expected utility
Equilibrium analysis
Gibilisco solves for Markov perfect equilibria, in which play in each active period depends solely on the level of grievances
I do wonder how philosophically Markovian the equilibrium here is. I want to interpret the relationship between grievances and the probability of mobilization success in terms of a coordination problem — past repression essentially creates a focal point, making it easier to turn people out for a revolt. But then the implicit underlying story there is one where past actions with no direct payoff relevance are affecting equilibrium selection in the present, violating the Markov spirit. So I think a “strong” Markovian would have to go with something like the final microfoundation Gibilisco gives on p. 1355, where repression has direct effects discouraging participation in the formal economy.
Low grievances
The first main result is that there’s no repression, mobilization, or independence along the path of play when grievances are low enough. The result is that grievances gradually dissipate until eventually hitting bottom, and the state stays together without the need for repression.
First let’s establish that this is an MPE when
Now think about whether this type of equilibrium is sustainable at
The chance of mobilization succeeding is now
, making it worthwhile if is high enough and is low enough.There is an imperative to mobilize now, because otherwise grievances will dip to
next period and then we will be stuck in the equilibrium where P has no credible threat and C maintains control forever. (I’m taking for granted that the equilibria characterized here are unique.)
A one-shot deviation to mobilization is weakly unprofitable for P iff
If Equation 3 fails, then equilibrium behavior at
Proceeding inductively this way, we can characterize a cutpoint
Medium grievances
At grievance levels above
Following Gibilisco’s notation, let
Now consider a state in between the thresholds,
P will mobilize. If C does nothing, the expected utility to P from mobilizing is
where the second inequality follows because .C does not prefer granting independence. Because granting independence yields a payoff of
, this follows from .C does not prefer repression. This is the trickiest one to prove, as it requires a comparison to a state with higher grievances where we haven’t necessarily figured out optimal behavior yet.
The first part of the proof (Lemma 7 in the appendix) is that if the equilibrium involves repressing with positive probability at
, then it cannot involve granting independence with positive probability at . Independence can never be granted in equilibrium if since then it’s better for C to just repress forever. Otherwise, if , then it’s better to grant independence today than to repress today (for net negative present payoff) and then grant independence tomorrow.Now consider a one-shot deviation to repression. Because
, this cannot be profitable for C if it would result in indefinite repression. So there must be some finite number of periods (perhaps just one) during which repression will be chosen. By the argument above, independence can never be chosen in state , so by process of elimination C must choose hands-off in state . Because , P will then mobilize for certain. But if C doesn’t want to repress when P is certain to mobilize at state , then it also shouldn’t want to repress when P is certain to mobilize at the lower-grievance state . Altogether, then, there cannot be a profitable one-shot deviation to repression.
High grievances
Now consider the other end of the spectrum, where grievances are very high,
At this extreme high grievance level, Assumptions 1 and 2 together ensure that C would not choose a hands-off policy. If perpetual repression is better than independence,
It’s a bit more complicated if
The necessity of mixing in equilibrium here is related to the argument in Mark Fey and Brad Smith’s working paper “Committing to Fight”, which unfortunately still has no public draft.
Part of why Gibilisco gets mixing here is the implicit assumption that it may take arbitrarily long for grievances to dissipate. I suspect the solution under high grievances would be simpler if there were simply some maximal feasible level of grievances. It’s a nice technical accomplishment that Gibilisco is able to solve the model even without being able to work backward from a highest possible level of grievance — though I do (genuinely) wonder how realistic it is to assume grievances can grow without bound. This also gets back to the question of just how philosophically Markovian we’re being here, in terms of not conditioning behavior on payoff-irrelevant histories.
On page 1362, Gibilisco interprets “cycles of repression and popular mobilization” observed in real-world cases as potentially reflective of the mixed strategy equilibrium here. I appreciate the effort to ground these in a Markovian model rather than some tit-for-tat folk theorem stuff (especially because the observed path of play under tit-for-tat ought to be all cooperation!) but I’m always a bit leery to attribute “sometimes this thing happens and other times this other thing happens” to mixed-strategy equilibria. Are the decision-makers really indifferent between their options at each point in time? (Or close enough to indifference that we can appeal to some kind of Harsanyi purification logic?)
Comparative statics
The comparative statics analysis is based on a restriction of the model with payoffs
This payoff formulation is the reason that Gibilisco doesn’t normalize
One result (Observation 1 in the paper) is that decentralization expands the conditions for the “low grievances” equilibrium, where the government chooses hands-off, the periphery does not mobilize, and eventually grievances dissipate. In the decentralization formulation, the relevant cutpoint (defined by Equation 4) turns into
The comparative statics for the other cutpoint are not so straightforward (Observation 2). There’s a bunch of different effects here:
Decentralization lowers the value of the “low grievances” outcome for the center, thereby lowering
. This would tend to lower , expanding the “high grievances” set.Decentralization reduces the credibility of the periphery’s threat to fight, pushing
upward (per above) and thus increasing . This would tend to increase , shrinking the “high grievances” set. Yet at extreme levels ( ), it would result in Assumption 1 being violated, such that all grievances are “small” ( ).Decentralization reduces the value of indefinite repression. Up to a point, this would tend to increase
, shrinking the “high grievances” set. However, this effect shuts off once the status quo is sufficiently unattractive for the center that it would rather grant independence than repress indefinitely.